SUMMARY OF OPERATIONS
Heads |
Features |
n |
iN,
iPerson, iNumber, iGender, uCase iWh
(for wh-phrases such as who and what) |
nExpl |
iN,
uPerson |
d |
iD |
v* |
iv,
uPerson, uNumber, uGender, Case:Acc |
C |
iC,
iQ |
CQ |
iC,
uQ |
Psv |
iAux,
uPerson, uNumber, uGender |
Prog, Perf |
iAux |
ToT |
iTense:None,
uPerson |
Tpres |
iTense:Pres,
uPerson, uNumber, uGender, Case:Nom |
Tpast |
iTense:Past,
uPerson, uNumber, uGender, Case:Nom |
Prog,
Perf, Psv |
AuxF |
Roots |
Roots
such as read and book which are categorized as verbs and
nominals, verbal roots can assign theta-roles |
Table 1 Basic
Heads and important features (i =
interpretable/valued, u = unvalued)
# |
Basic Operations
and principles |
Source
(if relevant) |
(1) |
Input Stream Each derivation
begins with an input list of lexical items, which are selected and Merged. |
|
(2) |
External
set-Merge Given syntactic
objects X and Y, form {X, Y}. |
Chomsky
2000, 2004 |
(3) |
Internal
set-Merge {….X….} {X,
{….X….}} l Select
an argument X in the accessible portion (not transferred) of an SO, and
internally set-Merge the argument X with the root. |
|
(3) |
Pair-Merge Given syntactic
objects X and Y, form <X, Y> , where X (or Y) is invisible to further
syntactic operations. |
|
(4) |
Categorization A root is
categorized when Labeled by a categorizer v, n, etc. |
Marantz
1997, Embick and Marantz 2008, Borer 2005a, 2005b, 2013; Chomsky 2013, 2015 |
(5) |
Theta-criterion An argument must
be assigned a theta-role on external-Merge. An argument cannot get a second
theta-role. |
Chomsky 1981, 2021 |
(6) |
Agree l A
probe (uF) on the root note searches for a matching
goal iF in its c-command domain. Agree(X[uF1],
Y[F1]) (X[F1], Y[F1]) l If a
probe with uF1 Agrees with a goal that has an identical uF1, the uF1 unify. Agree(X[uF1],
Y[uF1]), uF1 unify |
Chomsky
2001, Ginsburg & Fong (2019) |
|
FormCopy If NP X
c-commands NP Y, X and Y are identical in form, and if there no intervening
NP Z, Y can be interpreted as a Copy of X. A Copy in a Case position is
pronounced. |
Chomsky
2021 |
(7) |
Case: Basic Case configurations a.
Subject: {NP, TP} b.
Object: {v*, {R, NP}} c.
Object of P: {P, NP} d.
Possessor: {NP, NP} Case
is a reflex of phi-feature agreement. It appears at Spell-Out and its form is
subject to cross-linguistic and language-internal variation. |
Chomsky
2000, 2001, Marantz 2000, Bobaljik 2008 |
(7) |
The Box A
topicalized/focused phrase goes into a Box after external Merge with an SO. CQ
has access to the Box. |
Chomsky
2024 |
(8) |
Free Merge of
arguments {….NP1…..} {NP1,
{…. An
argument NP1 contained within an SO (that has not been
transferred) can be internally set-Merged with the root of the SO. |
Chomsky 2001, 2013, 2015 |
(9) |
Labeling a. Given
{X[F1], Y[F1]}, where F1 is a prominent feature, F1
labels. b. Given
{ c. Given
{X, YP}, X labels if it doesn’t have any uFs. |
Chomsky
2013, 2015 Mizuguchi
2017 |
(10) |
Transfer When
a phase head is Merged, the entire phase is transferred. |
Chomsky
2001, 2013, 2015 |
(11) |
Basic Spell Out
Rules Tense: T v*
R/Aux R/Aux+T Modal: T Modal T+Modal Passive: be -en v R be R+-en Progressive: be
-ing v* R be
R+-ing Perfective: have
-en v* R have
R+-en Interrogatives:
CQ N T CQ+T
N Thematization/Extraction:
N be+-en v R be N R+-en Irregular verb forms
are stored in a lexicon. |
Chomsky
1957 |
Table 2 Basic
Operations and Principles (R = Root)
References
Bobaljik, Jonathan
David. (2008). Where’s phi? Agreement as a postsyntactic
operation. In Daniel Harbour, David Adger & Susana
Béjar (Eds.), Phi theory: Phi features across modules and interfaces
(pp. 295-328). Oxford University Press.Borer, Hagit. 2005a. In name only. Structuring sense, Volume 1. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Borer,
Hagit. 2005b. The normal course of
events: Structuring sense, Volume 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Borer,
Hagit. 2013. Taking form: Structuring
sense, Volume 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 1957. Syntactic structures.
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on
government and binding: the Pisa lectures. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries. In
Roger Martin, David Michaels, and Juan Uriagereka
(eds.), Step by step: Essays on minimalism in honor of Howard Lasnik, 89-155. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In
Michael Kenstowicz
(ed.), Ken Hale: a life in language, 1-52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2004. Beyond explanatory
adequacy. In Adriana Belletti (ed), Structures and beyond: The cartography
of syntactic structures, Volume 3, 104-132. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2013. Problems of projection. Lingua
130. 33-49. DOI: 10.1016/j.lingua.2012.12.003
Chomsky, Noam. 2015. Problems of projections:
Extensions. Structures, strategies and beyond: Studies in honour of Adriana Belletti, ed. by Elisa Di Domenico,
Cornelia Hamann, and Simona Matteini, 1-16.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Chomsky, Noam. 2021. Minimalism: Where are we
now, and where can we hope to go. Gengo Kenkyu
160. 1-41.
Chomsky,
Noam. 2024. The miracle creed and SMT. In Matteo Greco & Davide Mocci
(eds.), A Cartesian dream: A geometrical account of syntax: In honor of
Andrea Moro, 17-40). Lingbuzz Press.
Embick,
David & Alec Marantz. 2008. Architecture and blocking. Linguistic Inquiry 39. 1-53.
Ginsburg,
Jason & Fong, Sandiway. 2019. Combining
linguistic theories in a Minimalist Machine. In Robert C. Berwick and Edward P.
Stabler (eds.), Minimalist Parsing, 39-69. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Marantz,
Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don’t try morphological analysis in the
privacy of your own lexicon. University
of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 4.2. 201-225.
Marantz, Alec. 2000. Case and licensing.
In Eric J. Reuland (ed.), Arguments and Case: Explaining Burzio’s
Generalization, 11-30. John Benjamins.
Mizuguchi,
Manabu. 2017. Labelability and interpretability. Studies
in Generative Grammar 27. 327-365.